In
sociology PhD program, we are encouraged to find research interests and then
decide on a research question. The methods we choose depend on what we are
interested in and how we approach them. Durkheim’s Suicide does not follow this usual path. Rather, he selected
suicide as a case study to “demonstrate
the possibility of sociology” (37), which treats social facts as things. Given the interest in this book,
this memo focuses on the methodological aspects of Suicide. Specifically, I discuss (1) Durkheim’s causality with a
comparison of Weber’s one, (2) his interpretation of statistics (means and
variances), and (3) his lack of interest in probability.
1. Causality
in Durkheim and Weber’s Sociology
Durkheim’s methodology is
often called methodological holism (Coleman
1986). This perspective treats macro-level social things as a unit of analysis
to explain other social phenomena. On the other hand, Weber is a founder of methodological individualism, in which we
explain macro-level associations focusing on individual’s actions. In addition
to this well-known distinction between them, another notable difference in
their sociological approach is their understanding of causality. To discuss
this point, it is helpful to use typologies of causality developed by John
Stuart Mill. Among them, Weber’s approach is the method of difference. This approach compares two cases that are the
same except for one trait. The assumption is close to the idea of a natural experiment,
or “imaginary experiment” (Smelser 1976: 69). Of course, experiments are often not
possible in social sciences, and some studies (including Weber’s work) look at
a few historical cases. Weber’s approach is historical, not statistical, but he
used this method, as we saw in the reading last week (Weber 1906=1978: 119).
In contrast, Durkeim
used so-called method of concomitant variation
(Smelser 1976: 63-64), which is simply a correlation between two variables
(such as suicide rate and solidarity) given a variety of cases. One contrast
between these two methods happens when we find third causes (Smelser 1976). On
the one hand, since the method of difference focuses on the difference caused
by the presence of one single cause, problems of third causes will not happen.
On the other hand, the method of concomitant variation allows the possibility
of third causes.
In modern statistics, we
control for these third variables to examine the effect of X on Y. Durkheim
attempted this without using statistics. For example, in detecting the effect
of religion on suicide, he controlled for influences of culture or race by
looking at different states in the same country (Germany or Switzerland). However,
he was not able to distinguish the effects of education and religion, because
they are strongly correlated. Instead, he found a distal cause, which is integration
(159), and argued that this explains the societal differences in suicide rates.
Well done.
We can be skeptical
about his conclusion, however. Jewish population has a lower suicide rate (154)
while their education tends to be higher (167). Durkheim picked up another
arbitrary explanation, arguing that it is because of their desire for knowledge
as “religious minorities”. If this hypothesis is correct, however, we can
speculate that Protestants and Catholics are also highly educated when they are
religious minorities in a given society. Unfortunately, this point was not
examined in the Suicide. As Smelser (1976:
107) critically argued, “unsystematic appeal to a third variable was built into
the logic of Durkheim’s theory.” To put it further, he was confident in his focus
on integration as the explanation (Sato 2010). One methodological advantage
using the method of difference is to control unobserved characteristics because
they are able to compare cases with only one difference, while the method of
concomitant variations is not. However, as Durkheim (1901=1982: 150) argued
elsewhere, the same effect always
corresponds to the same cause. In this sense, his discussion suggests that he
already fixed the causal relationship before observing the data. If some
anomaly happened, he added a third variable to arbitrarily solve the
contradiction.
2. Interpretation
of Means and Variance
Although Durkheim criticized Quetelet’s idea of the ‘average
man’[1], Hacking (1990: 178)
argued that he nevertheless “stayed in the Queteletian mould,” in a sense that he
still stuck with average rather than deviations (Sato 2010) or their similar
assumption that “the forces acting on people were like cosmic forces or
gravity” (Hacking 1990: 131). In Durkheim’s methodology, the forces are social (Hacking
1990: 177).
For Durkheim, who was interested in average rather
than variation, deviations from the mean reflect pathological states of society
(Hacking 1990: 178). In contrast, Galton was interested in the deviation
itself. For him, the normal is just average and deviation from the mean is
something we need to explain (Hacking 1990: 178, 184). This distinction has a persistent
influence on quantitative reasoning in contemporary sociology (Xie 2007). Quetelet’s
idea of ‘average man’ is close to what Mayr (2001) called ‘typological
thinking,’ which dates back its origin to Plato. This perspective focuses on
typical phenomena, and treats deviations from the mean as errors or nuisances.
Thus, this perspective considers heterogeneity within the population as
trivial.
In contrast, another approach towards population, ‘population
thinking,’ treats deviation as a serious subject to be explained (Xie 2007). According
to this perspective, a deviation is not a mismeasurement of reality. Rather, it
also reflects a part of reality. Galton, who developed regression and
correlation, belongs to this tradition. The latter perspective is dominant in
demography, or social demography, which is interested in heterogeneity across
subpopulation.[2]
3. Silence
about Probability
As Hacking (1990: 177) pointed out, Durkheim was not
interested in probability (or chance). This critique might be harsh given that
he did not have individual-level data and was not able to calculate standard
errors in his correlation estimates. On the other hand, however, his lack of
interest in probability is understandable because, unlike survey data, the data
he used targeted a whole society (vital statistics or census).
As argued, he thought that the same effect always corresponds to the same cause.
Also, he theorized that suicide is not a sum of individuals but influenced by
external factors. In this deterministic approach, he could justify the lack of
probability in this work. That being said, it is still worth pointing out that Suicide is the book that used statistics. Weber’s approach is
historical, but he does not assume these historical causes in a deterministic
way (Weber 1906=1978: 116). This contrast suggests that the distinction between
deterministic and probabilistic approaches is independent of which data
(statistical or historical) we use.
5. Conclusion
A summary of Durkheim’s methodology is shown below.
His methodology is often compared with that of Weber, typically through an
illustration of methodological holism versus individualism. Although important,
this distinction masks several important criteria taken by them. Their
methodology is different not only in the unit of analysis (collective versus
individual), but also in causality and statistical thinking. Also, Durkheim’s
quantitative reasoning is close to typological thinking, which makes contrasts
with population thinking.
It is hard to discuss Durkheim’s contribution to sociological
methodology (at least to me). His choice of methods of concomitant variations
to identify causality results in pursuing endless arbitrary third explanations.
His statistical thinking was mostly wrong. As a demographer, I take on the
population thinking rather than typological thinking. We can learn more from
reading Weber, especially for methodology. One contribution, however, is his focus
on social forces and methodological manifests that we should treat social facts
as things. This is a tentative
conclusion I have so far, after reading the Rules
and the Suicide.
Table Overview of Durkheim's methodology
Durkheim
|
Opposing ideas
|
|
Causality
|
Methods
of concomitant variations
|
Methods
of difference (Mill, Weber)
|
Quantitative
reasoning
|
Typological
thinking (Quetelet)
|
Population
thinking (Galton)
|
Statistical
thinking
|
Lack
of interest in probability (deterministic?)
|
Indeterministic
(Weber)
|
References
Coleman, James S. 1986. “Social
Theory, Social Research, and a Theory of Action.” American Journal of Sociology 91(6):1309–35.
Durkheim, Émile. 1901. Rules of the Sociological Method (2d
ed.) (W.D. Halls trans.) Free Press. 1982.
Hacking, Ian. 1990. The Taming of Chance. Cambridge
University Press.
Hauser, Philip M., and Otis D.
Duncan (Eds.) 1959. The Study of
Population: An Inventory and Appraisal, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Mayr, Ernst. 2001. “The
Philosophical Foundations of Darwinism.” Proceedings
of the American Philosophical Society 145(4):488–95.
Sato, Toshiki. 2010. Syakaigaku no Hoho [Methods in
Sociology]. Yuhikaku. [In Japanese]
Smelser, Neil J. 1976. Comparative
Methods in the Social Sciences. Prentice-Hall Inc.
Weber, Max. 1906. “The Logic of
Historical Explanation.” in Max Weber:
Selections in Translation. (W.G. Runciman, ed.; Eric Matthews, trans.)
Cambridge University Press, 1978. 111‐134.
Xie, Yu. 2007. “Otis Dudley
Duncan’s Legacy: The Demographic Approach to Quantitative Reasoning in Social
Science.” Research in Social
Stratification and Mobility 25(2):141–56.
[1] Statistically speaking,
his critique on Quetelet (300-306) was incorrect (Sato 2010: 103). He first
argued that Quetelet assumed that the invariability is found in some activities
with which the great majority of individuals is involved, and this idea is
wrong because the suicide rate, which is exceptional in population, is “even
more stable than that of general mortality” (303). Those who studied an
introduction to statistics know that the variability (standard deviation)
depends on sample size, not the variable of interest itself. Also, the suicide
rate is calculated by the number of incidences of suicide over a given
population, which is exactly the same as mean, or the idea of ‘average man’. This
point is also related to his silence about probability. He did not pay
attention to variation.
[2] One well-known
definition of demography is “the study of the size, territorial distribution,
and composition of population, changes therein, and the components of such
changes” (Hauser and Duncan 1959: 2).
No comments:
Post a Comment